Friday, February 5, 2021

Belgian euthanasia (study). Legal requirements are undermined or ignored. Euthanasia is out-of-control.

Alex Schadenberg
Executive Director, Euthanasia Prevention Coalition

A study by Belgian researchers and published in the Journal of Medicine and Philosophy on January 25, 2021, examines the practise of euthanasia in Belgium and concludes that legal requirements are being undermined and safeguards ignored. The study concludes that:
there are shortcomings in the Belgian euthanasia law, the application of that law, and the monitoring of euthanasia practice. This leads us to conclude that several of these shortcomings are structural and thus require more than simply increased oversight.

The study was conducted by Kasper Raus, Bert Vanderhaegen and Sigrid Sterckx from Ghent University and examines the official Belgian euthanasia data within the context of other studies that examine the application of the Belgian euthanasia law. This study is done by Belgian researchers who have been examining the Belgian euthanasia data for many years. One may disagree with the conclusion of the study but the data is impeccable.

Looking at key issues.

The study points out that since euthanasia was legalized in 2002 in Belgium, the debate on the issue has continued. There has been several legislative proposals to change the law since 2002. The study states:

All but two proposed amendments were voted down. The Euthanasia Law was first amended in 2005 to provide legal protection for pharmacists dispensing the lethal medication for the performance of euthanasia (Law of 10 November 2005). In 2014, the Euthanasia Law was amended again, this time to allow euthanasia for minors who are judged to have “capacity for discernment,” without setting an age limit (Law of 28 February 2014).
The study points out that there is a yearly increase in the number of euthanasia deaths, but the number of actual euthanasia deaths is unknown due to high percentage of unreported euthanasia deaths. The study states:

According to the latest official report, 2359 cases of euthanasia were reported in 2018 and 2656 cases in 2019 (Federal Control and Evaluation Commission for Euthanasia [FCECE], 2020). Given that 108.745 people died in Belgium in 2019, reported euthanasia accounts for 2.4 percent of all deaths. By contrast, the most recent anonymous physician survey study suggests that, for Flanders (the Dutch-speaking part of Belgium) in 2013, the number was 4.6 percent of all deaths (Chambaere et al., 2015). A follow-up study looking more closely into the euthanasia cases reported in the anonymous survey showed that only around 60 percent of them were reported to the FCECE (Dierickx et al., 2018). There is thus a significant extent of under reporting.

The study points out that the characteristics of those who die by euthanasia has changed. Euthanasia has become more common for people over the age of 80 who live in nursing homes. The study states:

The official reports of the FCECE likewise show a shift in euthanasia characteristics. The latest report (covering 2018 and 2019) shows an increase of reported euthanasia cases not only for unbearable psychological suffering, but also for so-called “polypathology,” which accounts for 17.4 percent of all euthanasia cases reported in 2019 and represents the second most common indication for receiving euthanasia (after cancer, which accounts for around 62 percent of all reported euthanasia cases) (FCECE, 2020).
Euthanasia based on "polypathology" means that the person is not necessarily dying but has multiple chronic conditions. The study defines "polypathology" as:
“the co-occurrence of multiple chronic or acute diseases and medical conditions within one person”
The study states that the growth in the practice of euthanasia does not necessarily signify a concern, but rather all people should be concerned about how the:
legal requirements of the euthanasia law that are intended to operate as safeguards and procedural guarantees in reality often fail to operate.

The researchers focus on three kinds of safeguards or procedural guarantees:

(1) the legally defined due care criteria for eligibility for euthanasia;

(2) the consultation of a second (and sometimes third) physician; and

(3) the reporting of euthanasia cases to the FCECE.
The legally defined criteria for eligibility for euthanasia.

The first issue is voluntariness. The study states:
How the voluntariness and well-considered nature of the request should be assessed is not stipulated in the Euthanasia Law, and no standardized tool is provided either by professional medical organizations or by the FCECE. This has given rise to the criticism that it is unclear how reliable the physician’s assessment of voluntariness can be in the absence of standardized assessment tools (Kim, De Vries, and Peteet, 2016).
The study points out that the requirement that the patient experience constant and unbearable suffering is a subjective criteria that can only be assessed by the patient. Physicians can be involved with the assessment, and can suggest ways to alleviate suffering, but the patient is not required to accept effective treatments. This is a subjective criteria.

The study discuss the criteria that a person must be experiencing a serious and incurable disorder caused by illness or accident. This does appear to be less subjective, but the study points out, who is to determine if the condition is serious? This is subjective because one person may consider their condition serious, while another may not consider the condition to be serious. There are also many incurable "disorders" that are related to disability. People with disabilities have rightly pointed out how these definitions focus on them.

The study questions the definition of the terminal illness. They point out that the Federal Control and Evaluation Commission for Euthanasia (FCECE) use a broad definition for the term illness.

Illustrations of potential overstretching

The study examine how the law has been interpreted and they suggest that there are three areas of overstretching of the law. They state:
The first illustration pertains to the criterion of incurability, the second concerns the legal requirements for patients experiencing psychological suffering, and the final illustration is that of so-called polypathology.

The first issue that the study examines is the application of the incurability requirement. They point out that euthanasia is being permitted for people who are curable but are refusing treatment. The authors refer to the recent FCECE report which stated:

When considering whether suffering can or cannot be alleviated, one has to take into account the patient’s right to refuse treatment or even palliative care, for example when this treatment has side effects or involves methods of administration he/she considers unbearable. (FCECE, 2020, 20; authors’ translation)
Similarily the Oregon assisted suicide law does not require a person to be terminally ill (within 6 months), but rather requires that a person would be terminally ill without treatment within 6 months.

The authors are not questioning the right to refuse treatment, they are questioning the approval of euthanasia, when effective treatment is possible. They stated:
Of course, we are not arguing that it would be permissible to interfere with patients’ rights to refuse treatment, which is a fundamental moral right (and is also enshrined in the Belgian Law on Patients’ Rights, 2002). Patients always maintain the possibility to refuse treatment, without having to justify this decision. However, such refusal should never automatically make a patient qualify for receiving euthanasia.
Psychological suffering caused by a psychiatric condition is also a contentious question. The law allows euthanasia for physical and psychological suffering but it does not define psychological suffering. The authors suggest that psychological suffering is being interpreted in an increasingly broader way. The study states:
Available empirical evidence and reports show that euthanasia is performed increasingly frequently in cases of psychological suffering (e.g., for schizophrenia, borderline disorder, or depression) (FCECE, 2020).
In 2017, the Flemish guideline stated that euthanasia for psychological suffering can only be done after the patient has tried all possible treatments. It recommended at least one year must pass before euthanasia for psychological suffering can be approved and it stated that if the patient refuses effective treatment, that this would invalidate their request for euthanasia. The authors point out that this is a new directive and its effect cannot be evaluated.

Polypathology

As stated earlier, "polypathology" that is, a combination of various conditions, has become the second most common reason for euthanasia in Belgium. The authors suggest that the problem with polypathology is the wide interpretation of its use.

The study explains that conditions included within the definition of polypathology include:
reduced eyesight which could result in increased social isolation, polyarthritis, reduced hearing to complete deafness that inhibits the person’s ability for human contact, early stage dementia, and incontinence (FCECE, 2020).
Several of these conditions are normal for elderly people to experience. Remember, approval for euthanasia, based on polypathology, does not require the person to be terminally ill. It is possible that someone who is losing their eyesight and hearing would be approved for euthanasia, as happened with the Belgian twins who were otherwise healthy but died by euthanasia out of fear of becoming blind.

The study points out that euthanasia based on "tired of living" is already being approved under the concept of euthanasia for polypathology. The study states:
Based on a broad understanding of polypathology, some commentators argue that the concept can also cover tiredness of life. In an interview with a Belgian newspaper, health law Professor Herman Nys argued that persons who are tired of life are able to receive euthanasia under the current Euthanasia Law because, due to their older age, they are likely to have several age-related conditions. In that same interview, the president of the FCECE admitted that such cases of euthanasia for tiredness of life are indeed already being reported to the Commission (Beel, 2011). This is problematic because these cases are likely not to meet the legal criteria.
A priori control: Consultation of one or two independent physicians.

The Belgian euthanasia law, like other euthanasia laws, requires that two independent physicians must be consulted before a euthanasia is approved, and in the case of psychiatric or child euthanasia, a third independent physician must be consulted with expertise in the area of concern.

The study points out that there are some serious concerns with the application of the law. According to the study:
In its 2018 report, the FCECE states that for polypathology, it considers any GP to be a specialist (FCECE, 2018). This has far-reaching implications. In 2019, polypathology represented 17.4 percent of all reported euthanasia cases and a staggering 47 percent of all reported nonterminal euthanasia cases (FCECE, 2020).

By way of example, we can refer to cases of euthanasia for psychiatric disorders. Because most patients suffering from psychiatric disorders are not imminently dying, two physicians will have to be consulted in such cases. The Euthanasia Law requires that the second consulted physician must be either a specialist in the condition the patient is suffering from, or a psychiatrist. In the case of euthanasia for psychiatric suffering, this frequently boils down to the same, as a specialist in the psychiatric condition will likely be a psychiatrist. However, if a patient with psychiatric suffering is diagnosed with another condition, the case can be reframed as a polypathology case; hence according to the FCECE, any GP can be the second consulted physician. Under these circumstances, euthanasia could thus be performed without any involvement of a psychiatrist; some research suggests that this is indeed occurring. A recent study by Dierickx et al. into the reported cases of euthanasia for psychiatric disorders found that: “Although it is a legal requirement to do so, a psychiatrist was not consulted in all cases with a diagnosis of psychiatric disorder” (Dierickx et al., 2017, 7).
The study suggests that since the FCECE allows a GP to be a specialist for conditions defined as polypathology, this has led to more conditions being defined as polypathology.

The study also points out that a 2015 court decision found that the opinions given by the consulted physicians are not binding. The outcome of this decision is that the attending physician is legally allowed to go ahead with the euthanasia, even if the consulted physician says No. This means that unless the case requires a psychiatric or pediatric assessment, there is no purpose for the second assessment. The study states:
Indeed, the fact that a physician could perform euthanasia and be in conformity with the legal requirements even when the consulted physicians report that in their opinion the patient blatantly is not suffering continuously and unbearably without prospect of improvement or clearly does not have a serious and incurable condition, has raised concern.
The concern about the lack of consultation in euthanasia deaths is found in the empirical data. The study states:
The occurrence of a lack of consultation of an independent physician is also confirmed by the most recent empirical study on the frequency of euthanasia. In a supplementary appendix to their article, Chambaere et al. (2015) report that in 2013 no independent physician was consulted in 7.4 percent of all cases under study (which amounts to 26 cases of a total of 349) (Chambaere et al., 2015). These cases were not reported to the FCECE because it claims that a second and third physician was consulted in every reported euthanasia case (FCECE, 2018).
Reporting to the Federal Control and Evaluation Commission for Euthanasia (FCECE)

The next concern examined is the posteriori control or after the death reporting system. The Belgian law, like the Netherlands, Canadian and American assisted suicide laws, require the physician who carries out the euthanasia to also be the physician who sends a report to the FCECE. This is a self-reporting system that is designed to protect physicians from the fear of prosecution. The study stated:
Taking into account that euthanasia concerns the intentional termination of someone’s life, from a legal perspective it would be perfectly logical to require a systematic notification of euthanasia cases to the medical examiner and the Public Prosecutor. This had, in fact, been the approach followed in The Netherlands from the early 1980s. However, when at the end of the 1990s initiatives were taken in The Netherlands and Belgium to draft a legal framework that would decriminalize euthanasia, that particular approach was considered too problematic. Practice in The Netherlands had shown that less than half of the estimated total number of cases of euthanasia were reported. It turned out that physicians dreaded the administrative burden and the high risk of prosecution (Gevers, 1996).
The study uses the phrase "high risk of prosecution" when in fact prosecution was rare in the Netherlands in the 1980' and 90's. Nonetheless, the study describes the current system of reporting in this way:
In Belgium, the Euthanasia Law requires that all euthanasia cases be reported to the FCECE. This Commission, which is neither a court nor an administrative body, is supposed to check for each reported case whether the legal criteria were met (Dierickx, 2003). It is composed of 16 members: eight physicians, four legal experts and four experts in the care for incurably ill patients.7 The requirement to report cases of euthanasia to a Commission of which half the members are physicians and which will not result in an automatic notification of the Public Prosecutor was considered essential to elicit the collaboration of physicians who perform euthanasia (Vansweevelt, 2003; Balthazar, 2003).
The study explains that the Belgian reporting system requires two parts, an anonymous part and the nonanonymous part. If the majority of the FCECE express concerns related to the anonymous part, the FCECE will examine the nonanonymous part that provides the names and information related to the death. The study explains that in 24.8% of the deaths the nonanonymous part of the report was examined in 2018/19. A referral of the report to the public prosecutor will only occur if two-thirds of the FCECE committee members agree. The report states:

In the 18 years since the law entered into force, only one case has been referred (FCECE, 2020). Important to note is that this euthanasia case was televised as an episode of the Australian show Dateline; hence, the specifics of this case came to public attention. Since the TV show made clear that at least one of the legal criteria for euthanasia had not been met, it would seem that the FCECE was left with no alternative but to refer the case to the Public Prosecutor.
The study later refers to the problem of the composition of the Committee. It is well-known that Dr Wim Distelmans is both the chair of the FCECE and one of the leading euthanasia doctors in Belgium. Clearly this is a question of "conflict of interest" since many of the most controversial euthanasia deaths are done by Dr Distelmans.

The study then examines the lack of response to the under-reporting of euthanasia in Belgium. The study points out that recent studies indicate that at least one-third of all Belgian euthanasia deaths go unreported. The study states:
Recent research suggests, for example, that roughly one in three cases of euthanasia is not reported (Dierickx et al., 2018). Moreover, comparisons of reported cases of euthanasia with unreported cases have found that “Unreported cases were generally dealt with less carefully than reported cases” (Smets et al., 2010, 4). The FCECE should be aware of this empirical research. One could wonder whether the FCECE or the Belgian Parliament should not acknowledge this as a problem that should be addressed.
More concerns about the Belgian reporting system.

As stated before, Belgium requires an Anonymous and a Nonanonymous reporting system that was designed to encourage a higher rate of euthanasia reports being submitted, and yet, Belgium has a higher rate of unreported euthanasia deaths, than the Netherlands, even though the Netherlands does not have an anonymous part of the report. The study points out that approximately 80% of the Netherlands euthanasia deaths are reported, while in Belgium it is estimated to be 67%.

In the 2018 report the FCECE acknowledges the unreported deaths when they state:

they are unable to compare the number of reported cases to the number of actually performed cases.
The study points out that Anonymous reporting makes it difficult to ensure that the basic legal requirements have been met. The study quotes the FCECE statement that:
“the demand for a strict and full independence of the consulted physician is already very difficult and in reality unattainable”

The study states:

When the attending and consulted physician share a last name, the familial tie could perhaps be suspected, but in other cases (no therapeutic relation and no hierarchical link), checking their dependence or independence is much less evident.

The study points out, as I stated earlier, that most of the Commission consists of practicing physicians who are monitoring their own cases. Since the Anonymous part of the report does not include the name of the physician, therefore it is impossible to know when a conflict of interest has occurred.

Another concern is the concise nature of the euthanasia report.

The study explains that compared to the Netherlands reporting system, the Belgian reports are very concise. The study illustrates the problem:

In one example, the attending physician reported only the following as a reason why the suffering could not be alleviated: “Illness was unsusceptible to further treatment. Further deterioration and decline were to be expected” (FCECE, 2016, 25; authors’ translation). However, such an answer amounts to a mere declaration that the suffering could not be alleviated and does not therefore provide a reason why the suffering could not be alleviated. The answer to the question “why could the suffering not be alleviated?” cannot simply be “because the suffering could not be alleviated.”
The study points out that the concise nature of the reporting misses key elements. It states:
More specifically, elements that cannot be directly checked include whether or not the patient was conscious at the time of the request, whether, for adult euthanized patients, the person was not legally incompetent, and whether or not the result of the consultation of the consulted physician(s) was communicated to the patient (Delbeke, 2012; Nys, 2016).
Another concern with the Belgian reporting system, as stated earlier, the opinion of the consulting physician does not need to be included. The study states:
A third matter of concern regarding the reporting form is that it does not require for the report of the consulted physician(s) to be included. The reporting physician merely summarizes the report of the consulted physician(s). The Commission is thus obliged to rely on the reporting physician to truthfully represent the advice of the consulted physician(s) (Balthazar, 2003).
The composition, role, and powers of the Commission.

As stated earlier, the FCECE is primarily made up of practising physicians, most of whom are directly involved in euthanasia. I also stated that the chair of the Commission is Dr Wim Distelmans, who is the leading euthanasia doctor in Belgium. The study states:
In its 2018 report, the FCECE describes a controversial case where life was terminated without the patient’s request. According to the FCECE, this case was heavily debated, with nine members in favor of referring the case to the Public Prosecutor and seven members against referral. As the two-thirds majority required for referral was not reached, the case was approved by the FCECE (2018). Hence, the question arises as to whether, instead of operating as a mechanism for societal monitoring, the Commission could operate as a control device of physicians, by physicians, for physicians, or perhaps even as a protection device?

...From the enactment of the Euthanasia Law to the end of 2019, 21,126 cases were reported to the Commission,10 yet the first time a case was ever referred to the Public Prosecutor was on 27 October 2015 (Nys, 2017).
The study reinforces its concerns by referring to the FCECE resignation letter from one of its members. The study states:
The fear that the FCECE operates as a shield that prevents problematic cases from being referred was fueled by the recent resignation of neurologist Dr. Ludo Vanopdenbosch (2018). In this letter of resignation, Dr. Vanopdenbosch, who stressed that he has no principled objections to euthanasia and that he has performed it several times, doubted both the FCEC’s objectivity and its independence. He explained in his letter that this could be illustrated with a striking example of a euthanasia case involving a patient suffering from advanced dementia and Parkinson disease. This case was reported to the FCECE and was discussed there on 5 September 2017. According to Dr. Vanopdenbosch, not a single legal criterion was met (e.g., there had not even been a request from the patient). After several hours of debate, the two-thirds majority required to send the case to the Public Prosecutor could not be found. This, Vanopdenbosch argues, proves that the Commission is obsolete. ... In the case at issue, nobody disputes the fact that the physician indeed intentionally ended the patient’s life and, moreover, that this was done at the request of the patient’s relatives. However, as far as we know, the judicial authorities have not taken any action against the physician in question.
The FCECE has prevented possible prosecutions by approving the death, even when legal requirements were not met. More recently, Belgian citizens are petitioning the public prosecutor to investigate cases that were already approved by the FCECE. There was the case of Tine Neys, who died by euthanasia for psychiatric reasons and the case of Tom Mortier's mother, who died by euthanasia based on depression.

The study points out that the FCECE admits in their 2018 report that they do approve cases that do not fit the criteria of the law. The study states:
In the 2018 FCECE report, one can read that: “Although in some rare cases one or more procedural requirements were not followed correctly, the euthanasia reports were nevertheless approved by the Commission after, every time, having assured itself that all the ‘essential conditions’ of the law were fulfilled: a competent patient, a written request, a medical condition without prospect of improvement, constant and unbearable suffering that cannot be alleviated and is caused by a serious and incurable condition” (FCECE, 2018, 26; authors’ translation). It should be noted that this claim is odd in view of the fact that, as mentioned above, in the same report the FCECE describes a case in which there was no written request.
The study concludes that the lack of oversight with the Belgian euthanasia law is structural. The study states:
Euthanasia, which involves the deliberate ending of a patient’s life, is a far-reaching and irreversible act that should be closely monitored. In this article, we have argued that there are shortcomings in the Belgian euthanasia law, the application of that law, and the monitoring of euthanasia practice. This leads us to conclude that several of these shortcomings are structural and thus require more than simply increased oversight.
First, the scope of the Euthanasia Law has been stretched from being used for serious and incurable illnesses to being used to cover tiredness of life. Second, the obligatory consultation of one or two independent physicians may fail to provide a real safeguard...The final authority to perform euthanasia lies with the attending physician who can perform it even against the (negative) advice of the consulted physicians. Third, the a posteriori control by the FCECE also raises concerns. The Commission is unable to check the fulfillment of various legal criteria, and it has substantial authority to (re) interpret the Euthanasia Law as it sees fit.

Due to the anonymity and the concise nature of the reporting form, the Commission is unable to check whether particular legal criteria are in fact met, even though that is its main task. Furthermore, due to the Commission’s composition and the authority it has taken upon itself, it might actually function as a shield, rather than a monitoring body. We have expressed the concern that the FCECE de facto has the power to change the interpretation of the Euthanasia Law unhindered by parliamentary, judicial, and societal control.

Furthermore, the observation that up until now the FCECE has only referred one case to the Public Prosecutor despite various indications that the legal criteria are not always met may lead one to question whether the a posteriori control mechanism is adequate.
After reading this exhaustive study, one must conclude that the Belgian euthanasia law is out-of-control. This is not only important for Belgium, but it is also important for other countries that are considering the legalization of euthanasia. Clearly, the Canadian euthanasia reporting system is inadequate, as it follows the same "self-reporting" system that is used in the Netherlands and Belgium. The Canadian system will likely never lead to a possible prosecution, and in the same way, unreported euthanasia deaths will likely run rampant in the system.

Unlike Belgium, there has yet to be a "third party" academic study to examine the compliance with the legal requirements in Canada. I make this statement while fully acknowledging that the Canadian government is currently expanding the scope of the euthanasia law without first doing a proper study of the original implementation of the law. This is completely irresponsible.

Belgium is not the only jurisdiction with oversight concerns, nonetheless, this study explains how the Belgian euthanasia law is currently the most abused death making law.

Link to the study (Link).

Thursday, February 4, 2021

Is death by euthanasia similar to death by drowning?

Alex Schadenberg
Executive Director, Euthanasia Prevention Coalition

Joan Bryden, reported for the Canadian Press about the Senate Committee on Legal and Constitutional Affairs hearings, who heard from expert witnesses this week concerning Bill C-7.

Bryden reports that Dr. Joel Zivot and Dr. Timothy Holland had different perspectives on how euthanasia drugs cause death.

Dr Zivot is a Canadian that is an associate professor of anesthesiology and critical care at Emory University in Atlanta Georgia. Bryden reported that Zivot explained to the Senate Committee that death by euthanasia is similar to death by drowning:
...based on his study of the autopsies of criminals in the United States who were executed by lethal injection, he said an assisted death "could be exceedingly painful and more like akin to drowning."

In 85 per cent of the execution cases, he said the lungs were twice their normal weight and full of water, the result of using Phenobarbital in the drug cocktail.

"It means that when a person dies by lethal injection, they basically drown ... more akin to death by waterboarding that we recognize to be cruel," he said, referring to a torture technique used to simulate drowning.

If autopsies were performed on people who've received MAID, Zivot said: "Based on my knowledge of pharmacology and familiarity with these drugs, I would suggest that there is a high likelihood that the same things would be found."

He contended that the drugs used in MAID procedures in Canada are similar to that used in U.S. executions, where Midazolam has replaced Phenobarbital.

Moreover, Zivot said Propofol, when used to anesthetize a patient for surgery, can cause a burning sensation in the lungs -- and that's using one tenth of the dose administered during MAID. But the use of the paralyzing drug in MAID means the patient can't show distress.

"To state that the death that the person feels is peaceful, well, this is unknowable or false ... That's a chemical myth that is put in place. That is a trick of what is actually happening here."
Euthanasia and capital punishment use similar lethal drug cocktails to cause death.

Bryden reports that Dr Holland vigorously disagreed and told the Senate Committee that:
for patients the procedure is "a relaxing drift into sleep."

"It is a beautiful and inspiring event,"
Holland then describes how the drugs are used differently for capital punishment than euthanasia, but in fact, the lethal drug regimen for capital punishment has evolved over the past few years.

Last September I wrote the article: Is death by lethal injection similar to drowning.

Dr Zivot's research indicates that death by euthanasia is similar to death by drowning. With euthanasia they use drugs to paralyze and sedate the person, making it impossible for the person to show distress as their lungs fill with fluid.

Netherlands government intends to extend euthanasia to children but not to people who are "tired of living", after the March election

Alex Schadenberg
Executive Director, Euthanasia Prevention Coalition

The DutchNews.nl reported yesterday that the government had drawn up a list of "controversial topics" that would be dealt with by the government after the March 17, 2021 election. One of the topics that was not on the list was expanding euthanasia to people who are "tired of living." 

The Netherlands Health Minister, Hugo de Jonge stated that the government intends to extend euthanasia to children, after the March election. It is likely that they decided that one euthanasia expansion category was enough for now. 

Sign and share the Petition opposing child euthanasia in the Netherlands (Link).

In July, 2020 I reported that a bill to extend euthanasia in the Netherlands to healthy people who are "tired of living" was submitted by Pia Dykstra (D66 party). An article by Janene Pieters in the NL Times reported that:

The legislative proposal allows people over the age of 75 who feel that they have come to the end of their life and have a persistent wish to die to ask for euthanasia.
Pieters also reported that Harry van der Molen (CDA party) told the Telegraaf news:
"As far as the CDA is concerned, there will be no completed life law, but we will tackle the causes of loneliness. Especially when people feel alone, abandoned or lost, they need attention or care."

The Dutchnews.nl reported on October 13 that de Jonge announced that the Dutch government will permit child euthanasia. According to the DutchNews.nl:

Health minister Hugo de Jonge has told MPs in a briefing that work is progressing on plans to make it possible to help terminally sick children aged between one and 12 to die, in limited circumstances.

De Jonge said that he wants to ensure there are ‘more legal guarantees for doctors’ who take the decision to end the life of a child, as well as transparency for healthcare staff and parents, and protection for the rights of children. 

Reports indicate that de Jonge plans to amend the euthanasia regulations, but not amend the law. DW news reported:

De Jonge added that current laws would not need to be amended. Rather, doctors would be exempted from prosecution for carrying out an approved euthanasia on a child.

The Netherlands law permits euthanasia for children as young as 12, with parental consent, people over the age of 16 can consent to euthanasia. The Groningen Protocol is a eugenic policy that permits euthanasia of newborns with disabilities. The proposed change would allow euthanasia for children (1 - 12).

Similar to the Groningen Protocol, that permits euthanasia of newborns with disabilities, the government would approve a set of guidelines to permit euthanasia for children under the age of 12 without actually changing the law.

The Dutch government wants to avoid the debate because of the contentious nature of the issue, but also because the four party coalition government includes two Christian parties who don't want to vote on the issue which may lead to their political defeat in the upcoming March 17, 2021 election. 

 

Wednesday, February 3, 2021

Let's offer humane and dignified living not lethal injection

Alex Schadenberg
Executive Director, Euthanasia Prevention Coalition

Psychiatrist, Dr Sephora Tang, and lawyer, Dylan McGuinty Jr, were published by the Ottawa Citizen on February 3, 2021, urging Canada to focus on humane and dignified living before offering a lethal injection.

Tang and McGuinty explain how Canada's euthanasia (MAiD) regime and it's expansion through Bill C-7 is changing healthcare and how this affects vulnerable Canadians:
Poor mental health, coupled with the stress of insufficient financial, personal and/or social supports, often leads to death wishes in people overwhelmed by their circumstances. Current pressure to remove the exclusion of mental illness as a sole eligibility criterion in Bill C-7 would make suicide prevention methods ineffective for individuals over the age of 18 who are contemplating suicide and suffering solely from psychological distress.
Dr Sephora Tang
They comment on how Bill C-7 will change Canada's euthanasia regime:
Bill C-7 will grant non-dying people assistance to end their lives after 90 days (less time if their assessor feels they may imminently lose their capacity to consent to their death) without at the same time requiring that they have reasonable access to supports needed to live a dignified life. As required by the bill, offering information about alternative care options is a far cry from being able to actually access care in a timely manner.

Lack of adequate supports is often a direct stressor that triggers suicidal death wishes in an individual, yet wait times for psychiatric services can often exceed the 90-day assessment period allotted by Bill C-7.
They make their point by commenting on a recent euthanasia death in Hamilton
The deplorable state of scarce supportive human resources has been made abundantly clear by the COVID-19 pandemic in long-term care facilities and in marginalized populations. A CBC story recently exposed the appalling conditions in which a 35-year-old Hamilton man had been living, surrounded by feces and urine, prior to having his life ended through MAiD.
Dylan McGuinty Jr
They state that society needs to offer humane and dignified living.
We would do better as a society to offer humane and dignified living before offering a lethal injection. While the federal government presumes in Bill C-7 that allowing 90 days for an assessment for MAiD for non-dying individuals is sufficient, clinical experience has revealed that some services, such as specialized residences for individuals requiring intensive support, can take years to access.

Without the necessary supports in place to parallel a permissive MAiD regime, individuals are left with the prospect of choosing between an assisted death or continuing the uphill struggle of living with inadequate supports; to place an individual in such a predicament is cruel and fundamentally unjust.
They comment on the recent United Nations Human Rights letter rejecting euthanasia for disability.
A recent report by UN human rights experts and special rapporteurs highlighted these concerns by saying: “People with disabilities condemned to live in poverty due to the lack of adequate social protection can decide to end their lives as a gesture of despair. Set against the legacy of accumulated disadvantages their ‘architecture of choice’ could hardly be said to be unproblematic.”
They conclude by urging Canadian politicians to pause on Bill C-7 and then to offer humane and dignified living before offering a lethal injection.
In truth, MAiD legislation affects us all. As the current pandemic has demonstrated, our state of health is fragile, especially when exposed to prolonged stress and circumstances outside our control. If we as a society do not invest and advocate for life-affirming health care services and social supports to provide dignified living to all, we may one day come calling for help and find the only accessible option offered is death. Perhaps we should pause for a moment and reflect on whether this is truly the kind of society we wish to build as a nation; what we sow today is what we shall reap tomorrow. 

Links to more information on Bill C-7.

  • Euthanasia (MAiD) deaths in Canada continue to increase (Link). 
  • Bill C-7 is delayed until February 2021 (Link). 
  • Bill C-7 must be defeated (Link). 

What the COVID Crisis Tells Us About the Dangers of Assisted Suicide

This article was published by the disability rights group, Not Dead Yet on February 2, 2021.

Diane Coleman, Not Dead Yet
By Diane Coleman

The COVID pandemic revealed that people with disabilities have been denied treatment for the virus due to their disabilities and pervasive biases about their “quality of life”. This denial of care raises the very real issue that persons with disabilities are and will face similar discrimination under assisted suicide laws.

Healthcare providers are the gatekeepers of assisted suicide in states where it’s legal, rendering a terminal prognosis, certifying lack of coercion, etc. Assisted suicide laws immunize providers (and other persons) from criminal and civil liability in the death of an individual. Careful examination of the language in these laws reveals the absence of meaningful safeguards. Nevertheless, public acceptance has largely depended on trust in medical providers’ willingness and ability to protect very ill individuals from mistakes, coercion and abuses, up to and including negligent or intentional homicide. The pandemic has demonstrated that such trust is misplaced.

Media Coverage of Discriminatory Denial of COVID Treatment

A recent article in The Hill (Is Oregon’s physician-assisted suicide law affecting disabled COVID-19 patients?, 12/25/2020) considered the possibility of a link between “Oregon’s decades-old physician-assisted suicide (PAS) law and recent efforts to deny life-saving care to COVID-19 patients with disabilities.”

National Public Radio reporter Joe Shapiro also covered examples of COVID treatment denials involving people with disabilities in Oregon: Oregon Hospitals Didn’t Have Shortages. So Why Were Disabled People Denied Care?, (12/21/2020) and As Hospitals Fear Being Overwhelmed By COVID-19, Do The Disabled Get The Same Access? (12/14/20). The latter article summarized a Harvard researcher:
A “vast majority” of doctors say people with a significant disability have a worse quality of life, according to a recent poll by Dr. Lisa Iezzoni, a Harvard Medical School professor and physician who studies health care disparities for people with disabilities. Her research […was] published in the journal Health Affairs in early 2021.
Unfortunately, discriminatory denial of COVID treatment is not unique to Oregon.

COVID Crisis Standards of Care Discriminate Unlawfully

In response to concerns about shortages of ventilators and other resources to treat COVID patients, many states, local authorities and medical facilities developed policies for allocating resources if there were shortages. These “crisis standards of care” included denial of treatment based on such criteria as:
  • loss of reserves in energy, physical ability, cognition and general health (WA) 
  • intellectual and cognitive disabilities (AL) 
  • cancer with a less than 10- year survival expectation (PA) 
  • individuals who use ventilators on a regular basis may have their ventilators removed and reallocated (KS).

In early 2020, disability advocates began filing formal discrimination complaints against these policies, which were serious enough for the Office for Civil Rights of the U.S. Dept. of Health & Human Services to issue a bulletin stating that:

[P]ersons with disabilities should not be denied medical care on the basis of stereotypes, assessments of quality of life, or judgments about a person’s relative “worth” based on the presence or absence of disabilities or age.
Settlements between the Office for Civil Rights and certain states have resulted in critical policy improvements, but other states have failed to change their policies to comply with federal laws prohibiting discrimination based on disability.

Racial Disparities in Healthcare Increase the Injustices and Risks

Last summer, leading disability rights organizations called for an investigation of an Austin Texas hospital’s conduct relating to Mr. Michael Hickson, a Black man with physical and cognitive disabilities caused by brain injury, who died at the hospital on June 11, 2020. A complaint to OCR stated, “[T]he hospital refused to provide him treatment for his COVID 19, because of his disabilities. One of the doctors, in response to Mrs. Hickson asking if the reason they would not treat him was because of his lack of quality of life due to his disabilities, responded yes.”

Racial disparities in denial of healthcare treatments also increase the dangers of assisted suicide. Leading Black Disabled activist Anita Cameron has explained:
“People of color and people from other marginalized communities are at risk from assisted suicide laws because racial disparities in healthcare:
  • Lead to limited health choices and poorer health outcomes.
  • Make it more likely that doctors will “write off” patients as terminal.
  • Make it less likely that patients can afford life-saving treatment.
  • Make it less likely that patients will receive adequate pain treatment.
With all this, it is clear that legalizing assisted suicide puts people of color, the elderly, people with disabilities and people of certain socioeconomic status at risk of death through mistakes, abuse and coercion.”
National Council on Disability Bioethics Series Documents Rampant Medical Discrimination Against People With Disabilities

The National Council on Disability issued a series of groundbreaking reports on medical discrimination against disabled people, stating:
Despite the growing understanding that disability is a normal part of the human experience, the lives of persons with disabilities continue to be devalued in medical decision-making. Negative biases and inaccurate assumptions about the quality of life of a person with a disability are pervasive in U.S. society and can result in the devaluation and disparate treatment of people with disabilities, and in the medical context, these biases can have serious and even deadly consequences.
These reports covered such topics as organ transplant eligibility, futility policies, “quality adjusted life years” value measures and assisted suicide. As “The Danger of Assisted Suicide Laws” states:
The idea that hastened death is a pathway to dignity for people facing physical decline reveals the public’s extreme disparagement of functional limitations and a perception that “dignity” is not possible for people who rely on supports, technology, or caregivers to be independent or alive. Many hold the attitude that a person with a disability may be better off dead than alive.
Conclusion

Advocacy organizations supporting assisted suicide laws have pushed for public acceptance based on a generalized trust that medical providers are both willing and able to protect very ill individuals from medical mistakes as well as coercion and abuse. But that trust is, in many cases, misplaced and, in all cases, unrealistic. Claims that there have been no abuses are patently false, but more cases would surface if these laws were not designed to hide them. Assisted suicide laws must be rejected. The so-called “safeguards” cannot protect older, ill and disabled people from the discriminatory attitudes that permeate society including, as COVID policies have shown us, the medical system on which all of us depend.


Tuesday, February 2, 2021

North Dakota debates assisted suicide bill HB 1415

Alex Schadenberg
Executive Director, Euthanasia Prevention Coalition

The assisted suicide lobby intends to legalize assisted suicide throughout the US. North Dakota is not a state that has debated assisted suicide in the past, but seven legislators have sponsored HB 1415, a bill to legalize assisted suicide in North Dakota.

HB 1415 is similar to the Oregon assisted suicide law.

Several states that have legalized assisted suicide, such as Oregon, Washington State and Hawaii, are now debating the expansion of their assisted suicide laws. If HB 1415 passes the assisted suicide lobby will move to expand it in future years.

The Hawaii assisted suicide law came into effect on January 1, 2019. Only one year after legalizing assisted suicide, the Hawaii legislature debated two assisted suicide law expansion bills and this year Hawaii is debating bill SB 323 to expand their assisted suicide law.

Legalizing assisted suicide gives medical professionals, the right in law, to prescribe lethal drug cocktails knowing that the person intends to use it to cause their death.

State laws should never give anyone the right in law to be involved with causing the death of another person. This is a dangerous public policy.

Links to important articles:

Monday, February 1, 2021

Tell Portugal's President to veto the euthanasia bill.

On Friday, January 29, the Portugal Parliament legalized euthanasia. President Marcelo de Sousa can veto the bill (Article about the bill).

Link to send your message to President de Sousa. https://www.presidencia.pt/?action=3

President Marcelo de Sousa

Email: belem@presidencia.pt

Dear President Marcelo de Sousa

I urge you to veto the euthanasia bill that recently passed in the Portuguese Parliament.

Euthanasia is a form of homicide. It allows medical practitioners to lethally inject a patient upon request.

Similar to Canada's euthanasia law, the bill allows lethal injection based on subjective not objective considerations. Even if the "suffering" can be alleviated, death may be permitted based on whether or not the person considers the treatment acceptable.

The term suffering also includes psychiatric suffering, which means, euthanasia for psychiatric conditions would be permitted when the person asking to be killed considers the treatment options unacceptable.

The term permanent injuries specifically permits euthanasia for people with disabilities.

United Nations experts published a press release on January 25, titled: Disability is not a reason to sanction medically assisted dying, which expresses alarm at a growing trend of nations, such as Portugal, enacting legislation enabling access to medically assisted dying based on having a disability or disabling conditions, including old age (Link to the Press Release). The Press release states:

“Disability should never be a ground or justification to end someone’s life directly or indirectly.”

Such legislative provisions would institutionalize and legally authorize ableism, and directly violate Article 10 of the UN Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, which requires States to ensure that persons with disabilities can effectively enjoy their inherent right to life on an equal basis with others.

The Portuguese Medical Association, stated in July, that it opposes euthanasia and informed the government that they will not permit doctors to participate in the euthanasia commission (the commission to approve euthanasia). At the same time, a group of 15 law professors, including Professor Jorge Miranda, known as the father of Portugal's Constitution, stated that the euthanasia bills are unconstitutional.

You were recently re-elected with 61% support from your citizens. This is your time to lead and protect your citizens.

Portugal needs to care for its people, not kill them.

I urge you to veto the euthanasia bill.

Alex Schadenberg
Executive Director, Euthanasia Prevention Coalition

Link to send your message to President de Sousa. Email: belem@presidencia.pt or https://www.presidencia.pt/?action=3

Belgian euthanasia law is broken, says academic study

This article was published by Mercatornet on February 1, 2021.

Michael Cook
By Michael Cook
Its scope is ever-widening and the safeguards are failing.
E
very once in a while, a bioethics article appears which is so powerful an indictment of injustice that it sends shivers up the spines of its readers. In 1949 Leo Alexander published “Medical Science under Dictatorship” in the New England Journal of Medicine, about the atrocities committed by Nazi doctors. In 1966 Henry K. Beecher published “Ethics and Clinical Research”, also in the NEJM, whose bland title belied its searing message about ethical catastrophes in contemporary American medicine.

Euthanasia in Belgium: Shortcomings of the Law and Its Application and of the Monitoring of Practice”, just published in the The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, may not be as sensational as these landmark articles, but it gives them a run for their money.

Since 2002 euthanasia laws in Belgium and the Netherlands have been models for legal reform elsewhere. Canada has followed them. Portugal is about to. Spain is moving in the same direction. In Belgium euthanasia accounts for an estimated 2.4 percent of all deaths, and much more in Flanders, the Dutch-speaking section of the country.

Yet the authors of the JMP article basically argue that Belgian euthanasia is broken ethically, administratively and legally. Its scope is ever-widening and the safeguards are failing. The commission in charge of overseeing doctors’ compliance with the law is ineffective or even complicit in a pro-euthanasia agenda. To document its stunning claims, it draws not on newspaper scandals but on thoroughly researched academic research over the past 20 years and the reports of the control commission itself.

The authors, Kasper Raus, Bert Vanderhaegen, and Sigrid Sterckx, are all associated with Ghent University. It should be stressed that Kasper Raus and Sigrid Sterckx do not oppose euthanasia as a theoretical possibility. But, to their dismay, they feel that the Belgian model is broken. They make three main assertions.

“First, the scope of the Euthanasia Law has been stretched from being used for serious and incurable illnesses to being used to cover tiredness of life.” Under the 2002 Belgian law, euthanasia for “tiredness of life” is not permitted. But doctors can circumvent the law by diagnosing “polypathology”– a jumble of ailments which nearly every elderly person has – and this will be deemed sufficient for euthanasia. “Polypathology” was the reason cited in 19.4 percent of all reported euthanasia cases in 2019 and a “staggering” 47 percent of all reported nonterminal cases.

“Second, the obligatory consultation of one or two independent physicians may fail to provide a real safeguard. Their tasks are quite limited, and, more importantly, their advice is not binding anyway. The final authority to perform euthanasia lies with the attending physician who can perform it even against the (negative) advice of the consulted physicians.”

Here is one example of how the system can be gamed. If euthanasia is requested for a psychiatric condition, a psychiatrist needs to be consulted. However, if the patient has another condition, the diagnosis can be redefined as “polypathology” and a GP can approve it, eliminating the need for a psychiatric consultation.

Third, “The Commission is unable to check the fulfilment of various legal criteria, and it has substantial authority to (re) interpret the Euthanasia Law as it sees fit.” In fact, “the Commission does not seem to act as a filter between physicians who perform euthanasia and the Public Prosecutor, but instead as a shield that prevents potentially problematic cases from being referred.”

Conflict of interest is baked into the composition of the 16-member evaluation committee. Eight of them must be doctors and many of them, including the chairman, Wim Distelmans, perform euthanasia regularly. So they end up checking each other’s files for irregularities. They are supposed to recuse themselves if one of their own cases comes up – but they don’t.

Nothing illustrates the ineffectiveness — or connivance — of the Commission better than its track record. In the 18 years since legalisation, it has only referred one case to the Public Prosecutor. And this case had been filmed by an Australian broadcaster and was so obviously in breach of the law that referral was needed to keep up appearances. The doctor was acquitted.

Furthermore, research suggests that as many as one in three cases of euthanasia in Flanders are never reported – making the statistics almost meaningless.

The Commission consistently defends the smooth operation of the law, asserting that despite glitches here and there regarding “non-essential’ features, the “essential conditions” are being upheld. But the authors point that there is no legal ground for this distinction. The Commission is arrogating to itself legislative powers which it does not have.

Policy-makers and politicians in Belgium ought to be horrified by the abysmal working of their country’s euthanasia law documented by these academics. But the authors are not optimistic. They conclude by saying that whether anyone will take them seriously remains to be seen.

Amazingly, none of this is news in Belgium. Euthanasia has become so normalised that its critics tend to be regarded as the eccentrics, not the practitioners. So Wim Distelmans has little trouble in batting away condemnation.

A TV station last year gave one of the authors of the JMP article, Sigrid Sterckx, a platform to air her complaints. Distelmans’s response in an op-ed reveals a lot about the smugness of the “euthanasia establishment” in Belgium.

“This does not happen lightly … doctors do a thorough self-check beforehand … When the Committee finds an error, it is almost always a procedural error, such as forgetting to enter the date of death … If, according to the doctor(s) involved in the euthanasia, the conditions are met and this has been confirmed in the registration document, the Commission has confidence in this.”
Belgian doctors are killing thousands of their patients every year and only one of them has ever been referred for prosecution and no one has ever been convicted. Does this sound fishy to Dr Distelmans? Not at all. “There is a huge taboo among doctors about ‘helping someone with their wish to die’. So it is never an ill-considered decision.”

Never? That’s right, never. The catchphrase “Trust me, I’m a doctor” has never sounded more paternalistic and more sinister.