Advocates of legalising euthanasia are desperate to argue
for the ethical equivalence of two acts:
1. The withdrawal of life sustaining support from a patient at that patient’s request; and
2. The administration of a lethal dose of a toxic substance to a patient at that person’s request.
The reason for their insistence on the moral equivalence of
the two acts is their desire to give ethical legitimacy to active
voluntary euthanasia - a ‘therapeutic’ approach to managing the end of
life that is almost everywhere condemned [1] - by its supposed similarity
to the withdrawal of life support from a dying patient; an ethically
acceptable medical approach under certain circumstances.
All life ends in death, but there are different forms of
death. Natural death occurs when the body’s physiological mechanisms
deteriorate spontaneously, usually under the influence of some disease, to
the point where they can no longer support function (life). Such deaths
may be sudden and unexpected or drawn out over a period of time.
Un-natural death occurs as the result of severe damage to the body’s physiological
systems as the result of external forces: motor vehicle accidents, consuming
poisons, blunt trauma and so on. These deaths may also be sudden or delayed.
Some people require life-sustaining assistance with the help
of equipment such as the artificial kidney or respirators. Sometimes this assistance becomes burdensome to the recipient and
they come to believe that they are not achieving anything worthwhile by
continuing with it. Under such circumstances, they are entitled under New
Zealand law to request that the procedure be terminated.
Normally there would be considerable discussion amongst the
various parties involved before going ahead with the act, including
informing the patient that there is a small possibility that they might
not die. When the assistance is removed, the patient’s functional status
will depend on how low the physiological status has fallen during the
period of life support. In some cases it may support life for weeks, months or
even years; in others, not at all. Nobody knows at that point in time.
When the patient dies, he or she dies a natural death which
timing depends on the ability of his or her bodily functions to support
life. In removing the support, the doctor’s motivation is not to cause the
patient’s death but to respect the patient’s wishes with regard to the
nature of the ongoing life support. If death does become imminent, the
attendants will do everything in their power short of killing them, to support
the patient during their terminal hours or days.
In contrast, when a doctor accedes to a patient’s request
for euthanasia, both the patient and the doctor understand that the
request is for an immediate termination of life. In the majority of such
cases, the patient’s physiological systems are still capable of
maintaining life – maybe even for years. The doctor, with the intent of
killing the patient, administers a lethal substance in a dose that
interferes fatally with the physiology of the body so that it can no
longer support function, and the patient dies by means of a precipitate
‘un-natural’ death. Should the doctor fail to bring about such an abrupt
termination, his actions would be judged a failure.
Seen in this light, it is clearly evident that the actions
of the medical attendants in the two scenarios are by no means equivalent.
They are governed by very different motives and expectations. The motive
of the medical staff in the first scenario(withdrawing support) is to unburden
the patient of interventions that are causing distress and failing to
facilitate his or her long term welfare. The result of actions taken in
this scenario is to allow the patient to die a natural death. The motive of
the medical staff in the second scenario (administering euthanasia) is to
relieve the patient’s fears, apprehensions and symptoms by killing him or
her. The result of the actions taken in the second scenario is to
precipitate an ‘unnatural’ death.
It is not possible to credibly argue the equivalence of the
two acts.
----------------------------------------------------------------------------------
[1] Including by the World Health Organisation, the World Medical Association, the American Medical Association, the British Medical Association, the Australian Medical Association and the New Zealand Medical Association.Dr David Richmond – emeritus professor of geriatric medicine in Auckland New Zealand
1 comment:
I should volunteer for a hospice so I can pour their morphine down the toilet. There's no justice like poetic justice.
Post a Comment