Wednesday, February 12, 2020

Victoria Australia’s ‘voluntary assisted dying’ law has come into effect; but were legislators right to think they could avoid the ‘slippery slope’?

This article was originally published in ABC Religion & Ethics and Bioethics Outlook (Plunkett Centre for Ethics).

Professor John Keown
By John Keown

Victoria’s law permitting physician-assisted suicide (PAS) and voluntary euthanasia (VE) came into force in June last year. Other states, particularly Western Australia, may soon follow suit.

All Australians, whether legislators or voters, would do well to reflect on the warning of former Prime Minister Paul Keating, when the bill was being debated in 2017, that VE is a threshold moment for Australia, and a threshold the country should not cross. He cautioned that, once termination of life is allowed, pressure will mount for further liberalisation on the ground that the law discriminates against those denied PAS and VE. “The experience of overseas jurisdictions,” he added, “suggests the pressures for further liberalisation are irresistible.”

His article provoked a critical response from ABC/RMIT “fact checkers,” who concluded that in most jurisdictions where the law had been relaxed “little has changed regarding what practices are allowed or who can access assisted dying.”

They were mistaken. My book Euthanasia, Ethics and Public Policy, provides extensive evidence from abroad confirming slippery slope concerns.

The slippery slope argument holds that PAS and VE should not be legalised because neither prescriptions for lethal drugs, nor lethal injections, can be effectively controlled by the law. This is for two distinct reasons: practical and logical.

Practically, it is not feasible either to craft legal criteria (such as “unbearable suffering” or “terminal illness”) with sufficient precision or, even if it were, to police them. Logically, the moral arguments for lethal prescriptions for the “terminally ill” are also arguments for lethal injections, and lethal injections for patients who are chronically ill and have longer to suffer.

Moreover, the moral case for lethal injections for competent patients is also a case for lethal injections for incompetent patients such as infants: the patient’s lack of autonomy does not cancel the doctor’s duty of beneficence. If some competent patients would be “better off dead” because of their suffering, so would some incompetent patients. There is, then, a logical link between voluntary and non-voluntary euthanasia.

The disturbing experience overseas illustrates the force of both the practical argument and of the logical argument. Permissive laws have failed to ensure effective control, whether in the Netherlands or Belgium (and now Canada) that permit VE and PAS, or in those US jurisdictions like Oregon that permit only PAS. Five points will show that the “fact checkers”' conclusion that “little has changed” is wide of the mark.

First, VE and PAS became legal in the Netherlands in 1984 (not 2002 as the “fact checkers” state) through a ruling of the Dutch Supreme Court. In 1996, illustrating the logical slope, the Dutch courts declared infanticide lawful. (The “fact checkers” rightly regard this as a liberalisation of the law, though they wrongly assert that infanticide “remains illegal.”)

Second, the “fact checkers” interpret “further liberalisation” to mean that a government has taken steps to expand access or legally protected activities. But this ignores the reality that the interpretation of the law may become more permissive, whether by courts, review committees or doctors, even absent statutory amendment. And this is what has happened in the Netherlands and Belgium.

Professor Theo Boer, for example, a former member of a Dutch euthanasia review committee, has changed his mind about the law. He points to the dramatic increase in numbers and to significant bracket creep, extending to patients with mental illness, disorders of old age, and dementia. Supply has stimulated demand, euthanasia has become normalised and there has been a paradigm shift. Some slopes, he now cautions, truly are slippery.

One may add that, since 1984, official Dutch surveys have shown that thousands of patients have been killed without an explicit request, and thousands of cases have not been reported by doctors to the review committees required to check each case. Why should we expect Victoria’s “review board” to be any more effective in ensuring that the legal criteria are met and that all cases are reported?

Boer’s writing, and that of other leading scholars critical of the Dutch experience such as Dr (now Justice) Neil Gorsuch, are not mentioned by the “fact checkers.” Also noteworthy is their failure to mention the Dutch government's proposal in 2016 to extend the law to allow elderly people who are simply “tired of life” to be given suicide pills by “death counsellors.”

Third, they note that Belgium relaxed its law to allow children to access euthanasia and state that this was the only liberalisation. Not so. Although the Belgian legislation was deliberately limited to VE, the review commission has decided to approve cases of PAS. And, like the Dutch committees, the commission has permitted an increasingly elastic interpretation of the criteria.

Fourth, they write that the Canadian government, having legalised VE and PAS, commissioned studies in relation to access for mature minors, the mentally ill and by advance directive, but that these are only “potential legislative changes.” True, but why commission such studies unless you are considering extending the law? And the existing criteria are already being challenged in court as too restrictive.

Fifth, they attach importance to the fact that the Oregon-style laws in the United States have not been extended to the chronically ill or to permit VE. However, they do not consider whether this may simply be political expediency until a critical mass of states has legalised PAS.

It makes tactical sense for anyone seeking to make a radical change in the law, and whose opponents will raise slippery slope concerns, to get their foot in the door through relatively conservative proposals before prizing the door open wider. The former governor of Washington state, Booth Gardner, said he supported an Oregon-style law in his state as a first step that would weaken the nation’s resistance and produce a cultural shift resulting in laxer laws.

Professor Yale Kamisar wrote in his classic utilitarian essay against legalisation 60 years ago that the arguments against further liberalisation are weaker than the arguments against legalisation, which is itself an argument against legalisation.

Keating’s concerns are, then, amply supported by the experience overseas. Sadly, the “fact checkers” are not alone in misunderstanding that experience, as should be evident to anyone who reads the majority (though not the minority) reports of the parliamentary committees in Victoria or Western Australia. Quite frankly, any legislators who think they can avoid the slippery slope have learned little from other jurisdictions.

John Keown is the Rose F. Kennedy Professor of Christian Ethics in the Kennedy Institute of Ethics at Georgetown University.

No comments:

Post a Comment